A blog on statistics, methods, philosophy of science, and open science. Understanding 20% of statistics will improve 80% of your inferences.

Showing posts with label Asking Questions. Show all posts
Showing posts with label Asking Questions. Show all posts

Monday, May 9, 2022

Tukey on Decisions and Conclusions

In 1955 Tukey gave a dinner talk about the difference between decisions and conclusions at a meeting of the Section of Physical and Engineering Science of the American Statistical Association. The talk was published in 1960. The distinction relates directly to different goals researchers might have when they collect data. This blog is largely a summary of his paper.

 


Tukey was concerned about the ‘tendency of decision theory to attempt to conquest all of statistics’. In hindsight, he needn’t have worried. In the social sciences, most statistics textbooks do not even discuss decision theory. His goal was to distinguish decisions from conclusions, to carve out a space for ‘conclusion theory’ to complement decision theory. He distinguishes decisions from conclusions.

 

In practice, making a decision means to ‘decide to act for the present as if’. Possible actions are defined, possible states of nature identified, and we make an inference about each state of nature. Decisions can be made even when we remain extremely uncertain about any ‘truth’. Indeed, in extreme cases we can even make decisions without access to any data. We might even decide to act as if two mutually exclusive states of nature are true! For example, we might buy a train ticket for a holiday three months from now, but also take out life insurance in case we die tomorrow.   

 

Conclusions differ from decisions. First, conclusions are established without taking consequences into consideration. Second, conclusions are used to build up a ‘fairly well-established body of knowledge’. As Tukey writes: “A conclusion is a statement which is to be accepted as applicable to the conditions of an experiment or observation unless and until unusually strong evidence to the contrary arises.” A conclusion is not a decision on how to act in the present. Conclusions are to be accepted, and thereby incorporated into what Frick (1996) calls a ‘corpus of findings’. According to Tukey, conclusions are used to narrow down the number of working hypotheses still considered consistent with observations. Conclusions should be reached, not based on their consequences, but because of their lasting (but not everlasting, as conclusions can now and then be overturned by new evidence) contribution to scientific knowledge.

 

Tests of hypotheses

 

According to Tukey, a test of hypotheses can have two functions. The first function is as a decision procedure, and the second function is to reach a conclusion. In a decision procedure the goal is to choose a course of action given an acceptable risk. This risk can be high. For example, a researcher might decide not to pursue a research idea after a first study, designed to have 80% power for a smallest effect size of interest, yields a non-significant result. The error rate is at most 20%, but the researcher might have enough good research ideas to not care.

 

The second function is to reach a conclusion. This is done, according to Tukey, by controlling the Type 1 and Type 2 error rate at ‘suitably low levels’ (Note: Tukey’s discussion of concluding an effect is absent is hindered somewhat by the fact that equivalence tests were not yet widely established in 1955 – Hodges & Lehman’s paper appeared in 1954). Low error rates, such as the conventions to use a 5% of 1% alpha level, are needed to draw conclusions that can enter the corpus of findings (even though some of these conclusions will turn out to be wrong, in the long run).

 

Why would we need conclusions?

 

One might reasonably wonder if we need conclusions in science. Tukey also ponders this question in Appendix 2. He writes “Science, in the broadest sense, is both one of the most successful of human affairs, and one of the most decentralized. In principle, each of us puts his evidence (his observations, experimental or not, and their discussion) before all the others, and in due course an adequate consensus of opinion develops.” He argues not for an epistemological reason, nor for a statistical reason, but for a sociological reason. Tukey writes: There are four types of difficulty, then, ranging from communication through assessment to mathematical treatment, each of which by itself will be sufficient, for a long time, to prevent the replacement, in science, of the system of conclusions by a system based more closely on today’s decision theory.” He notes how scientists can no longer get together in a single room (as was somewhat possible in the early decades of the Royal Society of London) to reach consensus about decisions. Therefore, they need to communicate conclusions, as “In order to replace conclusions as the basic means of communication, it would be necessary to rearrange and replan the entire fabric of science.” 

 

I hadn’t read Tukey’s paper when we wrote our preprint “The Epistemic and Pragmatic Function of Dichotomous Claims Based on Statistical Hypothesis Tests”. In this preprint, we also discuss a sociological reason for the presence of dichotomous claims in science. We also ask: “Would it be possible to organize science in a way that relies less on tests of competing theories to arrive at intersubjectively established facts about phenomena?” and similarly conclude: “Such alternative approaches seem feasible if stakeholders agree on the research questions that need to be investigated, and methods to be utilized, and coordinate their research efforts”.  We should add a citation to Tukey's 1960 paper.

 

Is the goal of an study a conclusion, a decision, or both?

 

Tukey writes he “looks forward to the day when the history and status of tests of hypotheses will have been disentangled.” I think that in 2022 that day has not yet come. At the same time, Tukey admits in Appendix 1 that the two are sometimes intertwined.

 

A situation Tukey does not discuss, but that I think is especially difficult to disentangle, is a cumulative line of research. Although I would prefer to only build on an established corpus of findings, this is simply not possible. Not all conclusions in the current literature are reached with low error rates. This is true both for claims about the absence of an effect (which are rarely based on an equivalence test against a smallest effect size of interest with a low error rate), as for claims about the presence of an effect, not just because of p-hacking, but also because I might want to build on an exploratory finding from a previous study. In such cases, I would like to be able to conclude the effects I build on are established findings, but more often than not, I have to decide these effects are worth building on. The same holds for choices about the design of a set of studies in a research line. I might decide to include a factor in a subsequent study, or drop it. These decisions are based on conclusions with low error rates if I had the resources to collect large samples and perform replication studies, but other times they involve decisions about how to act in my next study with quite considerable risk.

 

We allow researchers to publish feasibility studies, pilot studies, and exploratory studies. We don’t require every study to be a Registered Report of Phase 3 trial. Not all information in the literature that we build on has been established with the rigor Tukey associates with conclusions. And the replication crisis has taught us that more conclusions from the past are later rejected than we might have thought based on the alpha levels reported in the original articles. And in some research areas, where data is scarce, we might need to accept that, if we want to learn anything, the conclusions will always more tentative (and the error rates accepted in individual studies will be higher) than in research areas where data is abundant.

 

Even if decisions and conclusions can not be completely disentangled, reflecting on their relative differences is very useful, as I think it can help us to clarify the goal we have when we collect data. 

 

For a 2013 blog post by Justin Esarey, who found the distinction a bit less useful than I found it, see https://polmeth.org/blog/scientific-conclusions-versus-scientific-decisions-or-we%E2%80%99re-having-tukey-thanksgiving

 

References

Frick, R. W. (1996). The appropriate use of null hypothesis testing. Psychological Methods, 1(4), 379–390. https://doi.org/10.1037/1082-989X.1.4.379

Tukey, J. W. (1960). Conclusions vs decisions. Technometrics, 2(4), 423–433.

Uygun Tunç, D., Tunç, M. N., & Lakens, D. (2021). The Epistemic and Pragmatic Function of Dichotomous Claims Based on Statistical Hypothesis Tests. PsyArXiv. https://doi.org/10.31234/osf.io/af9by

 

 

 

 

 

Monday, January 20, 2020

Review of "The Generalizability Crisis" by Tal Yarkoni

A response to this blog by Tal Yarkoni is here.

In a recent preprint titled "The Generalizability Crisis", Tal Yarkoni examines whether the current practice of how psychologists generalize from studies to theories is problematic. He writes: “The question taken up in this paper is whether or not the tendency to generalize psychology findings far beyond the circumstances in which they were originally established is defensible. The case I lay out in the next few sections is that it is not, and that unsupported generalization lies at the root of many of the methodological and sociological challenges currently affecting psychological science.” We had a long twitter discussion about the paper, and then read it in our reading group. In this review, I try to make my thoughts about the paper clear in one place, which might be useful if we want to continue to discuss whether there is a generalizability crisis, or not.

First, I agree with Yarkoni that almost all the proposals he makes in the section “Where to go from here?” are good suggestions. I don’t think they follow logically from his points about generalizability, as I detail below, but they are nevertheless solid suggestions a researcher should consider. Second, I agree that there are research lines in psychology where modelling more things as random factors will be productive, and a forceful manifesto (even if it is slightly less practical than similar earlier papers) might be a wake up call for people who had ignored this issue until now.

Beyond these two points of agreement, I found the main thesis in his article largely unconvincing. I don’t think there is a generalizability crisis, but the article is a nice illustration of why philosophers like Popper abandoned the idea of an inductive science. When Yarkoni concludes that “A direct implication of the arguments laid out above is that a huge proportion of the quantitative inferences drawn in the published psychology literature are so inductively weak as to be at best questionable and at worst utterly insensible.” I am primarily surprised he believes induction is a defensible philosophy of science. There is a very brief discussion of views by Popper, Meehl, and Mayo on page 19, but their work on testing theories is proposed as a probable not feasible solution – which is peculiar, because these authors would probably disagree with most of the points made by Yarkoni, and I would expect at least somewhere in the paper a discussion comparing induction against the deductive approach (especially since the deductive approach is arguably the dominant approach in psychology, and therefore none of the generalizability issues raised by Yarkoni are a big concern). Because I believe the article starts from a faulty position (scientists are not concerned with induction, but use deductive approaches) and because Yarkoni provides no empirical support for any of his claims that generalizability has led to huge problems (such as incredibly high Type 1 error rates), I remain unconvinced there is anything remotely close to the generalizability crisis he so evocatively argues for. The topic addressed by Yarkoni is very broad. It probably needs a book length treatment to do it justice. My review is already way too long, and I did not get into the finer details of the argument. But I hope this review helps to point out the parts of the manuscript where I feel important arguments lack a solid foundation, and where issues that deserve to be discussed are ignored.

Point 1: “Fast” and “slow” approaches need some grounding in philosophy of science.


Early in the introduction, Yarkoni says there is a “fast” and “slow” approach of drawing general conclusions from specific observations. Whenever people use words that don’t exactly describe what they mean, putting them in quotation marks is generally not a good idea. The “fast” and “slow” approaches he describes are not, I believe upon closer examination, two approaches “of drawing general conclusions from specific observations”.

The difference is actually between induction (the “slow” approach of generalizing from single observations to general observations) and deduction, as proposed by for example Popper. As Popper writes “According to the view that will be put forward here, the method of critically testing theories, and selecting them according to the results of tests, always proceeds on the following lines. From a new idea, put up tentatively, and not yet justified in any way—an anticipation, a hypothesis, a theoretical system, or what you will—conclusions are drawn by means of logical deduction.”

Yarkoni incorrectly suggests that “upon observing that a particular set of subjects rated a particular set of vignettes as more morally objectionable when primed with a particular set of cleanliness-related words than with a particular set of neutral words, one might draw the extremely broad conclusion that ‘cleanliness reduces the severity of moral judgments’”. This reverses the scientific process as proposed by Popper, which is (as several people have argued, see below) the dominant approach to knowledge generation in psychology. The authors are not concluding that “cleanliness reduces the severity of moral judgments” from their data. This would be induction. Instead, they are positing that “cleanliness reduces the severity of moral judgments”, they collected data and performed and empirical test, and found their hypothesis was corroborated. In other words, the hypothesis came first. It is not derived from the data – the hypothesis is what led them to collect the data.

Yarkoni deviates from what is arguably the common approach in psychological science, and suggests induction might actually work: “Eventually, if the effect is shown to hold when systematically varying a large number of other experimental factors, one may even earn the right to summarize the results of a few hundred studies by stating that “cleanliness reduces the severity of moral judgments””. This approach to science flies right in the face of Popper (1959/2002, p. 10), who says: “I never assume that we can argue from the truth of singular statements to the truth of theories. I never assume that by force of ‘verified’ conclusions, theories can be established as ‘true’, or even as merely ‘probable’.” Similarly, Lakatos (1978, p. 2) writes: “One can today easily demonstrate that there can be no valid derivation of a law of nature from any finite number of facts; but we still keep reading about scientific theories being proved from facts. Why this stubborn resistance to elementary logic?” I am personally on the side of Popper and Lakatos, but regardless of my preferences, Yarkoni needs to provide some argument his inductive approach to science has any possibility of being a success, preferably by embedding his views in some philosophy of science. I would also greatly welcome learning why Popper and Lakatos are wrong. Such an argument, which would overthrow the dominant model of knowledge generation in psychology, could be impactful, although a-priori I doubt it will be very successful.

Point 2: Titles are not evidence for psychologist’s tendency to generalize too quickly.


This is a minor point, but I think a good illustration of the weakness of some of the main arguments that are made in the paper. On the second page, Yarkoni argues that “the vast majority of psychological scientists have long operated under a regime of (extremely) fast generalization”. I don’t know about the vast majority of scientists, but Yarkoni himself is definitely using fast generalization. He looked through a single journal, and found 3 titles that made general statements (e.g., “Inspiration Encourages Belief in God”). When I downloaded and read this article, I noticed the discussion contains a ‘constraint on generalizability’ in the discussion, following (Simons et al., 2017). The authors wrote: “We identify two possible constraints on generality. First, we tested our ideas only in American and Korean samples. Second, we found that inspiring events that encourage feelings of personal insignificance may undermine these effects.”. Is Yarkoni not happy with these two sentence clearly limiting the generalizability in the discussion?

For me, this observation raised serious concerns about the statement Yarkoni makes that, simply from the titles of scientific articles, we can make a statement about whether authors make ‘fast’ or ‘slow’ generalizations. One reason is that Yarkoni examined titles from a scientific article that adheres to the publication manual of the APA. In the section on titles, the APA states: “A title should summarize the main idea of the manuscript simply and, if possible, with style. It should be a concise statement of the main topic and should identify the variables or theoretical issues under investigation and the relationship between them. An example of a good title is "Effect of Transformed Letters on Reading Speed."”. To me, it seems the authors are simply following the APA publication manual. I do not think their choice for a title provides us with any insight whatsoever about the tendency of authors to have a preference for ‘fast’ generalization. Again, this might be a minor point, but I found this an illustrative example of the strength of arguments in other places (see the next point for the most important example). Yarkoni needs to make a case that scientists are overgeneralizing, for there to be a generalizability crisis – but he does so unconvincingly. I sincerely doubt researchers expect their findings to generalize to all possible situations mentioned in the title, I doubt scientists believe titles are the place to accurately summarize limits of generalizability, and I doubt Yarkoni has made a strong point that psychologists overgeneralize based on this section. More empirical work would be needed to build a convincing case (e.g., code how researchers actually generalize their findings in a random selection of 250 articles, taking into account Gricean communication norms (especially the cooperative principle) in scientific articles).

Point 3: Theories and tests are not perfectly aligned in deductive approaches.


After explaining that psychologists use statistics to test predictions based on experiments that are operationalizations of verbal theories, Yarkoni notes: “From a generalizability standpoint, then, the key question is how closely the verbal and quantitative expressions of one’s hypothesis align with each other.”

Yarkoni writes: “When a researcher verbally expresses a particular hypothesis, she is implicitly defining a set of admissible observations containing all of the hypothetical situations in which some measurement could be taken that would inform that hypothesis. If the researcher subsequently asserts that a particular statistical procedure provides a suitable test of the verbal hypothesis, she is making the tacit but critical assumption that the universe of admissible observations implicitly defined by the chosen statistical procedure (in concert with the experimental design, measurement model, etc.) is well aligned with the one implicitly defined by the qualitative hypothesis. Should a discrepancy between the two be discovered, the researcher will then face a choice between (a) working to resolve the discrepancy in some way (i.e., by modifying either the verbal statement of the hypothesis or the quantitative procedure(s) meant to provide an operational parallel); or (b) giving up on the link between the two and accepting that the statistical procedure does not inform the verbal hypothesis in a meaningful way.

I highlighted what I think is the critical point is in a bold font. To generalize from a single observation to a general theory through induction, the sample and the test should represent the general theory. This is why Yarkoni is arguing that there has to be a direct correspondence between the theoretical model, and the statistical test. This is true in induction.

If I want to generalize beyond my direct observations, which are rarely sampled randomly from all possible factors that might impact my estimate, I need to account for uncertainty in the things I have not observed. As Yarkoni clearly explains, one does this by adding random factors to a model. He writes (p. 7) “Each additional random factor one adds to a model licenses generalization over a corresponding population of potential measurements, expanding the scope of inference beyond only those measurements that were actually obtained. However, adding random factors to one’s model also typically increases the uncertainty with which the fixed effects of interest are estimated”. You don’t need to read Popper to see the problem here – if you want to generalize to all possible random factors, there are so many of them, you will never be able to overcome the uncertainty and learn anything. This is why inductive approaches to science have largely been abandoned. As Yarkoni accurately summarizes based on an large multi-lab study on verbal overshadowing by Alogna: “given very conservative background assumptions, the massive Alogna et al. study—an initiative that drew on the efforts of dozens of researchers around the world—does not tell us much about the general phenomenon of verbal overshadowing. Under more realistic assumptions, it tells us essentially nothing.” This is also why Yarkoni’s first practical recommendation on how to move forward is to not solve the problem, but to do something else: “One perfectly reasonable course of action when faced with the difficulty of extracting meaningful, widely generalizable conclusions from effects that are inherently complex and highly variable is to opt out of the enterprise entirely.”

This is exactly the reason Popper (among others) rejected induction, and proposed a deductive approach. Why isn’t the alignment between theories and tests raised by Yarkoni a problem for the deductive approach proposed by Popper, Meehl, and Mayo? The reason is that the theory is tentatively posited as true, but in no way believed to be a complete representation of reality. This is an important difference. Yarkoni relies on an inductive approach, and thus the test needs to be aligned with the theory, and the theory defines “a set of admissible observations containing all of the hypothetical situations in which some measurement could be taken that would inform that hypothesis.” For deductive approaches, this is not true.

For philosophers of science like Popper and Lakatos, a theory is not a complete description of reality. Lakatos writes about theories: “Each of them, at any stage of its development, has unsolved problems and undigested anomalies. All theories, in this sense, are born refuted and die refuted.” Lakatos gives the example that Newton’s Principia could not even explain the motion of the moon when it was published. The main point here: All theories are wrong. The fact that all theories (or models) are wrong should not be surprising. Box’s quote “All models are wrong, some are useful” is perhaps best known, but I prefer Box (1976) on parsimony: “Since all models are wrong the scientist cannot obtain a "correct" one by excessive elaboration. On the contrary following William Ockham (1285-1349) he should seek an economical description of natural phenomena. Just as the ability to devise simple but evocative models is the signature of the great scientist so overelaboration and overparameterization is often the mark of mediocrity (Ockham's knife).” He follows this up by stating “Since all models are wrong the scientist must be alert to what is importantly wrong. It is inappropriate to be concerned about mice when there are tigers abroad.”

In a deductive approach, the goal of a theoretical model is to make useful predictions. I doubt anyone believes that any of the models they are currently working on is complete. Some researchers might follow an instrumentalist philosophy of science, and don’t expect their theories to be anything more than useful tools. Lakatos’s (1978) main contribution to philosophy of science was to develop a way we deal with our incorrect theories, admitting that all needed adjustment, but some adjustments lead to progressive research lines, and others to degenerative research lines.

In a deductive model, it is perfectly fine to posit a theory that eating ice-cream makes people happy, without assuming this holds for all flavors, across all cultures, at all temperatures, and is irrespective of the amount of ice-cream eaten previously, and many other factors. After all, it is just a tentatively model that we hope is simple enough to be useful, and that we expect to become more complex as we move forward. As we increase our understanding of food preferences, we might be able to modify our theory, so that it is still simple, but also allows us to predict the fact that eggnog and bacon flavoured ice-cream do not increase happiness (on average). The most important thing is that our theory is tentative, and posited to allow us to make good predictions. As long as the theory is useful, and we have no alternatives to replace it with, the theory will continue to be used – without any expectation that is will generalize to all possible situations. As Box (1976) writes: “Matters of fact can lead to a tentative theory. Deductions from this tentative theory may be found to be discrepant with certain known or specially acquired facts. These discrepancies can then induce a modified, or in some cases a different, theory.” A discussion of this large gap between Yarkoni and deductive approaches proposed by Popper and Meehl, where Yarkoni thinks theories and tests need to align, and deductive approaches see theories as tentative and wrong, should be included, I think. 


Point 4: The dismissal of risky predictions is far from convincing (and generalizability is typically a means to risky predictions, not a goal in itself).


If we read Popper (but also on the statistical side the work of Neyman) we see induction as a possible goal in science is clearly rejected. Yarkoni mentions deductive approaches briefly in his section on adopting better standards, in the sub-section on making riskier predictions. I intuitively expected this section to be crucial – after all, it finally turns to those scholars who would vehemently disagree with most of Yarkoni’s arguments in the preceding sections – but I found this part rather disappointing. Strangely enough, Yarkoni simply proposes predictions as a possible solution – but since the deductive approach goes directly against the inductive approach proposed by Yarkoni, it seems very weird to just mention risky predictions as one possible solution, when it is actually a completely opposite approach that rejects most of what Yarkoni argues for. Yarkoni does not seem to believe that the deductive mode proposed by Popper, Meehl, and Mayo, a hypothesis testing approach that is arguably the dominant approach in most of psychology (Cortina & Dunlap, 1997; Dienes, 2008; Hacking, 1965), has a lot of potential. The reason he doubts severe tests of predictions will be useful is that “in most domains of psychology, there are pervasive and typically very plausible competing explanations for almost every finding” (Yarkoni, p. 19). This could be resolved if risky predictions were possible, which Yarkoni doubts.

Yarkoni’s criticism on the possibility of severe tests is regrettably weak. Yarkoni says that “Unfortunately, in most domains of psychology, there are pervasive and typically very plausible competing explanations for almost every finding.” From his references (Cohen, Lykken, Meehl) we can see he refers to the crud factor, or the idea that the null hypothesis is always false. As we recently pointed out in a review paper on crud (Orben & Lakens, 2019), Meehl and Lykken disagreed about the definition of the crud factor, the evidence of crud in some datasets can not be generalized to all studies in pychology, and “The lack of conceptual debate and empirical research about the crud factor has been noted by critics who disagree with how some scientists treat the crud factor as an “axiom that needs no testing” (Mulaik, Raju, & Harshman, 1997).”. Altogether, I am very unconvinced by this cursory reference to crud makes a convincing point that “there are pervasive and typically very plausible competing explanations for almost every finding”. Risky predictions seem possible, to me, and demonstrating the generalizability of findings is actually one way to perform a severe test.

When Yarkoni discusses risky predictions, he sticks to risky quantitative predictions. As explained in Lakens (2020), “Making very narrow range predictions is a way to make it statistically likely to falsify your prediction if it is wrong. But the severity of a test is determined by all characteristics of a study that increases the capability of a prediction to be wrong, if it is wrong. For example, by predicting you will only observe a statistically significant difference from zero in a hypothesis test if a very specific set of experimental conditions is met that all follow from a single theory, it is possible to make theoretically risky predictions.” I think the reason most psychologists perform studies that demonstrate the generalizability of their findings has nothing to do with their desire to inductively build a theory from all these single observations. They show the findings generalize, because it increases the severity of their tests. In other words, according to this deductive approach, generalizability is not a goal in itself, but a it follows from the goal to perform severe tests. It is unclear to me why Yarkoni does not think that approaches such as triangulation (Munafò & Smith, 2018) are severe tests. I think these approaches are the driving force between many of the more successful theories in social psychology (e.g., social identity theory), and it works fine.

Generalization as a means to severely test a prediction is common, and one of the goals of direct replications (generalizing to new samples) and conceptual replications (generalizing to different procedures). Yarkoni might disagree with me that generalization serves severity, not vice versa. But then what is missing from the paper is a solid argument why people would want to generalize to begin with, assuming at least a decent number of them do not believe in induction. The inherent conflict between the deductive approaches and induction is also not explained in a satisfactory manner.

Point 5: Why care about statistical inferences, if these do not relate to sweeping verbal conclusions?


If we ignore all points previous points, we can still read Yarkoni’s paper as a call to introduce more random factors in our experiments. This nicely complements recent calls to vary all factors you do not thing should change the conclusions you draw (Baribault et al., 2018), and classic papers on random effects (Barr et al., 2013; Clark, 1969; Cornfield & Tukey, 1956).

Yarkoni generalizes from the fact that most scientists model subjects as a random factor, and then asks why scientists generalize to all sorts of other factors that were not in their models. He asks “Why not simply model all experimental factors, including subjects, as fixed effects”. It might be worth noting in the paper that sometimes researchers model subjects as fixed effects. For example, Fujisaki and Nishida (2009) write: “Participants were the two authors and five paid volunteers” and nowhere in their analyses do they assume there is any meaningful or important variation across individuals. In many perception studies, an eye is an eye, and an ear is an ear – whether from the author, or a random participant dragged into the lab from the corridor.

In other research areas, we do model individuals as a random factor. Yarkoni says we model stimuli as a random factor because: “The reason we model subjects as random effects is not that such a practice is objectively better, but rather, that this specification more closely aligns the meaning of the quantitative inference with the meaning of the qualitative hypothesis we’re interested in evaluating”. I disagree. I think we model certain factor as random effects because we have a high prior these factors influence the effect, and leaving them out of the model would reduce the strength of our prediction. Leaving them out reduces the probability a test will show we are wrong, if we are wrong. It impacts the severity of the test. Whether or not we need to model factors (e.g., temperature, the experimenter, or day of the week) as random factors because not doing so reduces the severity of a test is a subjective judgments. Research fields need to decide for themselves. It is very well possible more random factors are generally needed, but I don’t know how many, and doubt it will ever be as severe are the ‘generalizability crisis’ suggests. If it is as severe as Yarkoni suggests, some empirical demonstrations of this would be nice. Clark (1973) showed his language-as-fixed-effect fallacy using real data. Barr et al (2013) similarly made their point based on real data. I currently do not find the theoretical point very strong, but real data might convince me otherwise.

The issues about including random factors is discussed in a more complete, and importantly, applicable, manner in Barr et al (2013). Yarkoni remains vague on which random factors should be included and which not, and just recommends ‘more expansive’ models. I have no idea when this is done satisfactory. This is a problem with extreme arguments like the one Yarkoni puts forward. It is fine in theory to argue your test should align with whatever you want to generalize to, but in practice, it is impossible. And in the end, statistics is just a reasonably limited toolset that tries to steer people somewhat in the right direction. The discussion in Barr et al (2013), which includes trade-offs between converging models (which Yarkoni too easily dismisses as solved by modern computational power – it is not solved) and including all possible factors, and interactions between all possible factors, is a bit more pragmatic. Similarly, Cornfield & Tukey (1956) more pragmatically list options ranging from ignoring factors altogether, to randomizing them, or including them as a factor, and note “Each of these attitudes is appropriate in its place. In every experiment there are many variables which could enter, and one of the great skills of the experimenter lies in leaving out only inessential ones.” Just as pragmatically, Clark (1973) writes: “The wide-spread capitulation to the language-as-fixed-effect fallacy, though alarming, has probably not been disastrous. In the older established areas, most experienced investigators have acquired a good feel for what will replicate on a new language sample and what will not. They then design their experiments accordingly.” As always, it is easy to argue for extremes in theory, but this is generally uninteresting for an applied researcher. It would be great if Yarkoni could provide something a bit more pragmatic about what to do in practice than his current recommendation about fitting “more expansive models” – and provides some indication where to stop, or at least suggestions what an empirical research program would look like that tells us where to stop, and why. In some ways, Yarkoni’s point generalizes the argument that most findings in psychology do not generalize to non-WEIRD populations (Henrich et al., 2010), and it has the same weakness. WEIRD is a nice acronym, but it is just a completely random collection of 5 factors that might limit generalizability. The WEIRD acronym functions more as a nice reminder that boundary conditions exist, but it does not allow us to predict when they exist, or when they matter enough to be included in our theories. Currently, there is a gap between the factors that in theory could matter, and the factors that we should in practice incorporate. Maybe it is my pragmatic nature, but without such a discussion, I think the paper offers relatively little progress compared to previous discussions about generalizability (of which there are plenty).

Conclusion


A large part of Yarkoni’s argument is based on the fact that theories and tests should be closely aligned, while in a deductive approach based on severe tests of predictions, models are seen as simple, tentative, and wrong, and this is not considered a problem. Yarkoni does not convincingly argue researchers want to generalize extremely broadly (although I agree papers would benefit from including Constraints on Generalizability statements a proposed by Simons and colleagues (2017), but mainly because this improves falsifiability, not because it improves induction), and even if there is the tendency to overclaim in articles, I do not think this leads to an inferential crisis. Previous authors have made many of the same points, but in a more pragmatic manner (e.g., Barr et al., 2013m Clark, 1974,). Yarkoni fails to provide any insights into where the balance between generalizing to everything, and generalizing to factors that matter, should lie, nor does he provide an evaluation of how far off this balance research areas are. It is easy to argue any specific approach to science will not work in theory – but it is much more difficult to convincingly argue it does not work in practice. Until Yarkoni does the latter convincingly, I don’t think the generalizability crisis as he sketches it is something that will keep me up at night.



References


Baribault, B., Donkin, C., Little, D. R., Trueblood, J. S., Oravecz, Z., Ravenzwaaij, D. van, White, C. N., Boeck, P. D., & Vandekerckhove, J. (2018). Metastudies for robust tests of theory. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 115(11), 2607–2612. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1708285114

Barr, D. J., Levy, R., Scheepers, C., & Tily, H. J. (2013). Random effects structure for confirmatory hypothesis testing: Keep it maximal. Journal of Memory and Language, 68(3). https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jml.2012.11.001

Box, G. E. (1976). Science and statistics. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 71(356), 791–799. https://doi.org/10/gdm28w

Clark, H. H. (1969). Linguistic processes in deductive reasoning. Psychological Review, 76(4), 387–404. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0027578

Cornfield, J., & Tukey, J. W. (1956). Average Values of Mean Squares in Factorials. The Annals of Mathematical Statistics, 27(4), 907–949. https://doi.org/10.1214/aoms/1177728067

Cortina, J. M., & Dunlap, W. P. (1997). On the logic and purpose of significance testing. Psychological Methods, 2(2), 161.

Dienes, Z. (2008). Understanding psychology as a science: An introduction to scientific and statistical inference. Palgrave Macmillan.

Fujisaki, W., & Nishida, S. (2009). Audio–tactile superiority over visuo–tactile and audio–visual combinations in the temporal resolution of synchrony perception. Experimental Brain Research, 198(2), 245–259. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00221-009-1870-x

Hacking, I. (1965). Logic of Statistical Inference. Cambridge University Press.

Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A. (2010). Most people are not WEIRD. Nature, 466(7302), 29–29.

Lakens, D. (2020). The Value of Preregistration for Psychological Science: A Conceptual Analysis. Japanese Psychological Review. https://doi.org/10.31234/osf.io/jbh4w

Munafò, M. R., & Smith, G. D. (2018). Robust research needs many lines of evidence. Nature, 553(7689), 399–401. https://doi.org/10.1038/d41586-018-01023-3

Orben, A., & Lakens, D. (2019). Crud (Re)defined. https://doi.org/10.31234/osf.io/96dpy

Simons, D. J., Shoda, Y., & Lindsay, D. S. (2017). Constraints on Generality (COG): A Proposed Addition to All Empirical Papers. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 12(6), 1123–1128. https://doi.org/10.1177/1745691617708630

Sunday, November 24, 2019

Do You Really Want to Test a Hypothesis?


I’ve uploaded one of my favorite lectures in the my new MOOC “Improving Your Statistical Questions” to YouTube. It asks the question whether you really want to test a hypothesis. A hypothesis is a very specific tool to answer a very specific question. I like hypothesis tests, because in experimental psychology it is common to perform lines of research where you can design a bunch of studies that test simple predictions about the presence or absence of differences on some measure. I think they have a role to play in science. I also think hypothesis testing is widely overused. As we are starting to do hypothesis tests better (e.g., by preregistering our predictions and controlling our error rates in more severe tests) I predict many people will start to feel a bit squeamish as they become aware that doing hypothesis tests as they were originally designed to be used isn’t really want they want in their research. One of the often overlooked gains in teaching people how to do something well, is that they finally realize that they actually don’t want to do it.

The lecture “Do You Really Want to Test a Hypothesis” aims to explain which question a hypothesis tests asks, and discusses when a hypothesis tests answers a question you are interested in. It is very easy to say what not to do, or to point out what is wrong with statistical tools. Statistical tools are very limited, even under ideal circumstances. It’s more difficult to say what you can do. If you follow my work, you know that this latter question is what I spend my time on. Instead of telling you optional stopping can’t be done because it is p-hacking, I explain how you can do it correctly through sequential analysis. Instead of telling you it is wrong to conclude the absence of an effect from p > 0.05, I explain how to use equivalence testing­­. Instead of telling you p-values are the devil, I explain how they answer a question you might be interested in when used well. Instead of saying preregistration is redundant, I explain from which philosophy of science preregistration has value. And instead of saying we should abandon hypothesis tests, I try to explain in this video how to use them wisely. This is all part of my ongoing #JustifyEverything educational tour. I think it is a reasonable expectation that researchers should be able to answer at least a simple ‘why’ question if you ask why they use a specific tool, or use a tool in a specific manner.

This might help to move beyond the simplistic discussion I often see about these topics. If you ask me if I prefer frequentist of Bayesian statistics, or confirmatory or exploratory research, I am most likely to respond (see Wikipedia). It is tempting to think about these topics in a polarized either-or mindset – but then you would miss asking the real questions. When would any approach give you meaningful insights? Just as not every hypothesis test is an answer to a meaningful question, so will not every exploratory study provide interesting insights. The most important question to ask yourself when you plan a study is ‘when will the tools you use lead to interesting insights’? In the second week of my MOOC I discuss when effects in hypothesis tests could be deemed meaningful, but the same question applies to exploratory or descriptive research. Not all exploration is interesting, and we don’t want to simply describe every property of the world. Again, it is easy to dismiss any approach to knowledge generation, but it is so much more interesting to think about which tools will lead to interesting insights. And above all, realize that in most research lines, researchers will have a diverse set of questions that they want to answer given practical limitations, and they will need to rely on a diverse set of tools, limitations and all.

In this lecture I try to explain what the three limitations are of hypothesis tests, and the very specific question they try to answer. If you like to think about how to improve your statistical questions, you might be interested in enrolling in my free MOOC Improving Your Statistical Questions”.




Sunday, November 3, 2019

The Value of Preregistration for Psychological Science: A Conceptual Analysis


This blog is an excerpt of an invited journal article for a special issue of Japanese Psychological Review, that I am currently one week overdue with (but that I hope to complete soon). I hope this paper will raise the bar in the ongoing discussion about the value of preregistration in psychological science. If you have any feedback on what I wrote here, I would be very grateful to hear it, as it would allow me to improve the paper I am working on. If we want to fruitfully discuss preregistration, researchers need to provide a clear conceptual definition of preregistration, anchored in their philosophy of science.

For as long as data has been used to support scientific claims, people have tried to selectively present data in line with what they wish to be true. In his treatise ‘On the Decline of Science in England: And on Some of its Cases’ Babbage (1830) discusses what he calls cooking: “One of its numerous processes is to make multitudes of observations, and out of these to select those only which agree or very nearly agree. If a hundred observations are made, the cook must be very unlucky if he can not pick out fifteen or twenty that will do up for serving.” In the past researchers have proposed solutions to prevent bias in the literature. With the rise of the internet it has become feasible to create online registries that ask researchers to specify their research design and the planned analyses. Scientific communities have started to make use of this opportunity (for a historical overview, see Wiseman, Watt, & Kornbrot, 2019).

Preregistration in psychology has been a good example of ‘learning by doing’. Best practices are continuously updated as we learn from practical challenges and early meta-scientific investigations into how preregistrations are performed. At the same time, discussions have emerged about what the goal of preregistration is, whether preregistration is desirable, and what preregistration should look like across different research areas. Every practice comes with costs and benefits, and it is useful to evaluate whether and when preregistration is worth it. Finally, it is important to evaluate how preregistration relates to different philosophies of science, and when it facilitates or distracts from goals scientists might have. The discussion about benefits and costs of preregistration has not been productive up to now because there is a general lack of a conceptual analysis of what preregistration entails and aims to accomplish, which leads to disagreements that are easily resolved when a conceptual definition would be available. Any conceptual definition about a tool that scientists use, such as preregistration, must examine the goals it achieves, and thus requires a clearly specified view on philosophy of science, which provides an analysis of different goals scientists might have. Discussing preregistration without discussing philosophy of science is a waste of time.

What is Preregistration For?


Preregistration has the goal to transparently prevent bias due to selectively reporting analyses. Since bias in estimates only occurs in relation to a true population parameter, preregistration as discussed here is limited to scientific questions that involve estimates of population values from samples. Researchers can have many different goals when collecting data, perhaps most notably theory development, as opposed to tests of statistical predictions derived from theories. When testing predictions, researchers might want a specific analysis to yield a null effect, for example to show that including a possible confound in an analysis does not change their main results. More often perhaps, they want an analysis to yield a statistically significant result, for example so that they can argue the results support their prediction, based on a p-value below 0.05. Both examples are sources of bias in the estimate of a population effect size. In this paper I will assume researchers use frequentist statistics, but all arguments can be generalized to Bayesian statistics (Gelman & Shalizi, 2013). When effect size estimates are biased, for example due to the desire to obtain a statistically significant result, hypothesis tests performed on these estimates have inflated Type 1 error rates, and when bias emerges due to the desire to obtain a non-significant test result, hypothesis tests have reduced statistical power. In line with the general tendency to weigh Type 1 error rates (the probability of obtaining a statistically significant result when there is no true effect) as more serious than Type 2 error rates (the probability of obtaining a non-significant result when there is a true effect), publications that discuss preregistration have been more concerned with inflated Type 1 error rates than with low power. However, one can easily think of situations where the latter is a bigger concern.

If the only goal of a researcher is to prevent bias it suffices to make a mental note of the planned analyses, or to verbally agree upon the planned analysis with collaborators, assuming we will perfectly remember our plans when analyzing the data. The reason to write down an analysis plan is not to prevent bias, but to transparently prevent bias. By including transparency in the definition of preregistration it becomes clear that the main goal of preregistration is to convince others that the reported analysis tested a clearly specified prediction. Not all approaches to knowledge generation value prediction, and it is important to evaluate if your philosophy of science values prediction to be able to decide if preregistration is a useful tool in your research. Mayo (2018) presents an overview of different arguments for the role prediction plays in science and arrives at a severity requirement: We can build on claims that passed tests that were highly capable of demonstrating the claim was false, but supported the prediction nevertheless. This requires that researchers who read about claims are able to evaluate the severity of a test. Preregistration facilitates this.

Although falsifying theories is a complex issue, falsifying statistical predictions is straightforward. Researchers can specify when they will interpret data as support for their claim based on the result of a statistical test, and when not. An example is a directional (or one-sided) t-test testing whether an observed mean is larger than zero. Observing a value statistically smaller or equal to zero would falsify this statistical prediction (as long as statistical assumptions of the test hold, and with some error rate in frequentist approaches to statistics). In practice, only range predictions can be statistically falsified. Because resources and measurement accuracy are not infinitely large, there is always a value close enough to zero that is statistically impossible to distinguish from zero. Therefore, researchers will need to specify at least some possible outcomes that would not be considered support for their prediction that statistical tests can pick up on. How such bounds are determined is a massively understudied problem in psychology, but it is essential to have falsifiable predictions.

Where bounds of a range prediction enable statistical falsification, the specification of these bounds is not enough to evaluate how highly capable a test was to demonstrate a claim was wrong. Meehl (1990) argues that we are increasingly impressed by a prediction, the more ways a prediction could have been wrong.  He writes (1990, p. 128): “The working scientist is often more impressed when a theory predicts something within, or close to, a narrow interval than when it predicts something correctly within a wide one.” Imagine making a prediction about where a dart will land if I throw it at a dartboard. You will be more impressed with my darts skills if I predict I will hit the bullseye, and I hit the bullseye, than when I predict to hit the dartboard, and I hit the dartboard. Making very narrow range predictions is a way to make it statistically likely to falsify your prediction, if it is wrong. It is also possible to make theoretically risky predictions, for example by predicting you will only observe a statistically significant difference from zero in a hypothesis test if a very specific set of experimental conditions is met that all follow from a single theory. Regardless of how researchers increase the capability of a test to be wrong, the approach to scientific progress described here places more faith in claims based on predictions that have a higher capability of being falsified, but where data nevertheless supports the prediction. Anyone is free to choose a different philosophy of science, and create a coherent analysis of the goals of preregistration in that framework, but as far as I am aware, Mayo’s severity argument currently provides one of the few philosophies of science that allows for a coherent conceptual analysis of the value of preregistration.

Researchers admit to research practices that make their predictions, or the empirical support for their prediction, look more impressive than it is. One example of such a practice is optional stopping, where researchers collect a number of datapoints, perform statistical analyses, and continue the data collection if the result is not statistically significant. In theory, a researcher who is willing to continue collecting data indefinitely will always find a statistically significant result. By repeatedly looking at the data, the Type 1 error rate can inflate to 100%. Even though in practice the inflation will be smaller, optional stopping strongly increases the probability that a researcher can interpret their result as support for their prediction. In the extreme case, where a researcher is 100% certain that they will observe a statistically significant result when they perform their statistical test, their prediction will never be falsified. Providing support for a claim by relying on optional stopping should not increase our faith in the claim by much, or even at all. As Mayo (2018, p. 222) writes: “The good scientist deliberately arranges inquiries so as to capitalize on pushback, on effects that will not go away, on strategies to get errors to ramify quickly and force us to pay attention to them. The ability to register how hunting, optional stopping, and cherry picking alter their error-probing capacities is a crucial part of a method’s objectivity.” If researchers were to transparently register their data collection strategy, readers could evaluate the capability of the test to falsify their prediction, conclude this capability is very small, and be relatively unimpressed by the study. If the stopping rule keeps the probability of finding a non-significant result when the prediction is incorrect high, and the data nevertheless support the prediction, we can choose to act as if the claim is correct because it has been severely tested. Preregistration thus functions as a tool to allow other researchers te transparently evaluate the severity with which a claim has been tested.

The severity of a test can also be compromised by selecting a hypothesis based on the observed results. In this practice, known as Hypothesizing After the Results are Known (HARKing, Kerr, 1998) researchers look at their data, and then select a prediction. This reversal of the typical hypothesis testing procedure makes the test incapable of demonstrating the claim was false. Mayo (2018) refers to this as ‘bad evidence, no test’. If we choose a prediction from among the options that yield a significant result, the claims we make base on these ‘predictions’ will never be wrong. In philosophies of science that value predictions, such claims do not increase our confidence that the claim is true, because it has not yet been tested. By preregistering our predictions, we transparently communicate to readers that our predictions predated looking at data, and therefore that the data we present as support of our prediction could have falsified our hypothesis. We have not made our test look more severe by narrowing the range of our predictions after looking at the data (like the Texas sharpshooter who draws the circles of the bullseye after shooting at the wall of the barn). A reader can transparently evaluate how severely our claim was tested.

As a final example of the value of preregistration to transparently allow readers to evaluate the capability of our prediction to be falsified, think about the scenario described by Babbage at the beginning of this article, where a researchers makes multitudes of observations, and selects out of all these tests only those that support their prediction. The larger the number of observations to choose from, the higher the probability that one of the possible tests could be presented as support for the hypothesis. Therefore, from a perspective on scientific knowledge generation where severe tests are valued, choosing to selectively report tests from among many tests that were performed strongly reduces the capability of a test to demonstrate the claim was false. This can be prevented by correcting for multiple testing by lowering the alpha level depending on the number of tests.
The fact that preregistration is about specifying ways in which your claim could be false is not generally appreciated. Preregistrations should carefully specify not just the analysis researchers plan to perform, but also when they would infer from the analyses that their prediction was wrong. As the preceding section explains, successful predictions impress us more when the data that was collected was capable of falsifying the prediction. Therefore, a preregistration document should give us all the required information that allows us to evaluate the severity of the test. Specifying exactly which test will be performed on the data is important, but not enough. Researchers should also specify when they will conclude the prediction was not supported. Beyond specifying the analysis plan in detail, the severity of a test can be increased by narrowing the range of values that are predicted (without increasing the Type 1 and Type 2 error rate), or making the theoretical prediction more specific by specifying detailed circumstances under which the effect will be observed, and when it will not be observed.

When is preregistration valuable?


If one agrees with the conceptual analysis above, it follows that preregistration adds value for people who choose to increase their faith in claims that are supported by severe tests and predictive successes. Whether this seems reasonable depends on your philosophy of science. Preregistration itself does not make a study better or worse compared to a non-preregistered study. Sometimes, being able to transparently evaluate a study (and its capability to demonstrate claims were false) will reveal a study was completely uninformative. Other times we might be able to evaluate the capability of a study to demonstrate a claim was false even if the study is not transparently preregistered. Examples are studies where there is no room for bias, because the analyses are perfectly constrained by theory, or because it is not possible to analyze the data in any other way than was reported. Although the severity of a test is in principle unrelated to whether it is pre-registered or not, in practice there will be a positive correlation that is caused by the studies where the ability to evaluate how capable these studies were to demonstrate a claim was false is improved by transparently preregistering, such as studies with multiple dependent variables to choose from, which do not use standardized measurement scale so that the dependent variable can be calculated in different ways, or where additional data is easily collected, to name a few.

We can apply our conceptual analysis of preregistration to hypothetical real-life situations to gain a better insight into when preregistration is a valuable tool, and when not. For example, imagine a researcher who preregisters an experiment where the main analysis tests a linear relationship between two variables. This test yields a non-significant result, thereby failing to support the prediction. In an exploratory analysis the authors find that fitting a polynomial model yields a significant test result with a low p-value. A reviewer of their manuscript has studied the same relationship, albeit in a slightly different context and with another measure, and has unpublished data from multiple studies that also yielded polynomial relationships. The reviewer also has a tentative idea about the underlying mechanism that causes not a linear, but a polynomial, relationship. The original authors will be of the opinion that the claim of a polynomial relationship has passed a less severe test than their original prediction of a linear prediction would have passed (had it been supported). However, the reviewer would never have preregistered a linear relationship to begin with, and therefore does not evaluate the switch to a polynomial test in the exploratory result section as something that reduces the severity of the test. Given that the experiment was well-designed, the test for a polynomial relationship will be judged as having greater severity by the reviewer than by the authors. In this hypothetical example the reviewer has additional data that would have changed the hypothesis they would have preregistered in the original study. It is also possible that the difference in evaluation of the exploratory test for a polynomial relationship is based purely on a subjective prior belief, or on the basis of knowledge about an existing well-supported theory that would predict a polynomial, but not a linear, relationship.

Now imagine that our reviewer asks for the raw data to test whether their assumed underlying mechanism is supported. They receive the dataset, and looking through the data and the preregistration, the reviewer realizes that the original authors didn’t adhere to their preregistered analysis plan. They violated their stopping rule, analyzing the data in batches of four and stopping earlier than planned. They did not carefully specify how to compute their dependent variable in the preregistration, and although the reviewer has no experience with the measure that has been used, the dataset contains eight ways in which the dependent variable was calculated. Only one of the eight ways in which the dependent variable yields a significant effect for the polynomial relationship. Faced with this additional information, the reviewer believes it is much more likely that the analysis testing the claim was the result of selective reporting, and now is of the opinion the polynomial relationship was not severely tested.

Both of these evaluations of how severely a hypothesis was tested were perfectly reasonable, given the information reviewer had available. It reveals how sometimes switching from a preregistered analysis to an exploratory analysis does not impact the evaluation of the severity of the test by a reviewer, while in other cases a selectively reported result does reduce the perceived severity with which a claim has been tested. Preregistration makes more information available to readers that can be used to evaluate the severity of a test, but readers might not always evaluate the information in a preregistration in the same way. Whether a design or analytic choice increases or decreases the capability of a claim to be falsified depends on statistical theory, as well as on prior beliefs about the theory that is tested. Some practices are known to reduce the severity of tests, such as optional stopping and selective reporting analyses that yield desired results, and therefore it is easier to evaluate how statistical practices impact the severity with which a claim is tested. If a preregistration is followed through exactly as planned then the tests that are performed have desired error rates in the long run, as long as the test assumptions are met. Note that because long run error rates are based on assumptions about the data generating process, which are never known, true error rates are unknown, and thus preregistration makes it relatively more likely that tests have desired long run error rates. The severity of a tests also depends on assumptions about the underlying theory, and how the theoretical hypothesis is translated into a statistical hypothesis. There will rarely be unanimous agreement on whether a specific operationalization is a better or worse test of a hypothesis, and thus researchers will differ in their evaluation of how severely specific design choices tests a claim. This once more highlights how preregistration does not automatically increase the severity of a test. When it prevents practices that are known to reduce the severity of tests, such as optional stopping, preregistration leads to a relative increase in the severity of a test compared a non-preregistered study. But when there is no objective evaluation of the severity of a test, as is often the case when we try to judge how severe a test was based on theoretical grounds, preregistration merely enables a transparent evaluation of the capability of a claim to be falsified.